Edinburgh Research Archive logo

Edinburgh Research Archive

University of Edinburgh homecrest
View Item 
  •   ERA Home
  • Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences, School of
  • Philosophy
  • Philosophy PhD thesis collection
  • View Item
  •   ERA Home
  • Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences, School of
  • Philosophy
  • Philosophy PhD thesis collection
  • View Item
  • Login
JavaScript is disabled for your browser. Some features of this site may not work without it.

Plato's philosophical terminology: a history of words central to the ontology of his middle dialogues

View/Open
HerrmannFG_1999redux.pdf (53.92Mb)
Date
1999
Author
Herrmann, Fritz-Gregor
Metadata
Show full item record
Abstract
 
 
The purpose of this thesis is to provide preliminaries for a better understanding of central parts of Plato's philosophy. Its method is a combination of traditional diachronic semantics and the study of the literary and social contexts of words which may be termed pragmatics. Its justification, it is hoped, is provided by an application of the results of those studies to a portion of Platonic text which is, in parts, reinterpreted in the light of some new findings. The point of departure of the investigation undertaken is a passage from one of the dialogues of Plato's middle period which is generally assumed to contain the essence of his thoughts on matters ontological at the time of composition: Phaedo lOOd - 105e. From this text, a number of significant terms, most of them recurring in other dialogues of similar date, have been selected: fiSXSXSlV, 7tapstvai, 7tpOG£lV(Xl, fevetvai, sI8ck;, 'l5sa and some of their cognates; the histories of these terms have been traced, from their earliest occurrence in extant Greek literature, usually Homer, through the various authors and genres of epic, lyric and tragic poetry, historical, philosophical, medical and rhetorical writings, to the early dialogues of Plato himself. In the course of investigation it seemed appropriate to study the nouns 8t§OQ and 'l5ea in greater detail and to a degree approaching comprehensiveness, for two reasons: on the one hand, their semantic development is more marked and variegated, and therefore deserved more careful scrutiny; on the other, scholarly opinion, which has been taken into account throughout, is more divided as to the meaning and senses of these two nouns than with any of the other terms selected. For the same reason, it was deemed necessary to translate by far the majority of pre-Platonic occurrences of the two nouns in their contexts - that often required interpretation and discussion which may at first seem to be mere diversions - a measure not required in the case of the verbs under consideration. That in itself is a first result: nouns are more readily employed with extensions in meaning than verbs; they are more likely to acquire a fixity in application which may amount to a technical terminology. The difference in status and importance of the nouns over against the verbs is reflected in the separate arrangement of the material in Parts I and II.
 
Part III consists of an application of some the results yielded by the semantic studies of the individual words in Parts I and II. It is in the nature of the exercise that many of the J developments traced in Parts I and II are not made use of in Part III; however, it was felt that unless a complete study of all the various actual contexts prior in time were undertaken, it would not be possible to determine with certainty the meaning and connotations of any given term in any given text. The effort was not in vain, as it can be shown with fair precision not only what the terms selected actually meant with Plato but more importantly, which literary and intellectual contexts Plato derived his philosophical terminology from: being able to determine to whom Plato reacted in his thoughts, and with whom he was in dialogue in his writings, is more important than bare linguistic reconstruction of 'meaning'.
 
We see Plato in the central philosophical passage of the central dialogue Phaedo in interaction with three at least partly distinct parties of pre-Socratic philosophers: Anaxagoras and his followers, the Pythagoreans, and Democritus. While most of that conforms with received opinion, reaction to Democritus at that early a stage in Plato's writing career is not usually assumed. That in itself, and the use Plato makes of the thoughts of his predecessors in fusing and correcting their assumptions while adapting their language to his own purposes may prompt us to reconsider some commonly held views on Plato's ontology.
 
However, the study here attempted is intended to be preliminary in nature; the application to a Platonic text in Part III is to be understood as one example only of how the semantic investigations of Parts I and II may be applied to the dialogues of Plato and other near contemporary philosophical texts.
 
URI
http://hdl.handle.net/1842/26600
Collections
  • Philosophy PhD thesis collection

Library & University Collections HomeUniversity of Edinburgh Information Services Home
Privacy & Cookies | Takedown Policy | Accessibility | Contact
Privacy & Cookies
Takedown Policy
Accessibility
Contact
feed RSS Feeds

RSS Feed not available for this page

 

 

All of ERACommunities & CollectionsBy Issue DateAuthorsTitlesSubjectsPublication TypeSponsorSupervisorsThis CollectionBy Issue DateAuthorsTitlesSubjectsPublication TypeSponsorSupervisors
LoginRegister

Library & University Collections HomeUniversity of Edinburgh Information Services Home
Privacy & Cookies | Takedown Policy | Accessibility | Contact
Privacy & Cookies
Takedown Policy
Accessibility
Contact
feed RSS Feeds

RSS Feed not available for this page